The Infinite Hotel

The Infinite Hotel

Posers and Puzzles

Cookies help us deliver our Services. By using our Services or clicking I agree, you agree to our use of cookies. Learn More.

In your face

Joined
21 Aug 04
Moves
55993
22 Jul 06

Originally posted by AThousandYoung
How about the limit of f(x) = x/x as x => infinity? That gives you 1 person per room.

How did you decide infinity/infinity = 0, Jim?
I just thought that any # divided by infinity = 0. I stand corrected dude. 🙂

G

B is for bye bye

Joined
09 Apr 06
Moves
27526
23 Jul 06

Originally posted by AThousandYoung
How about the limit of f(x) = x/x as x => infinity? That gives you 1 person per room.

How did you decide infinity/infinity = 0, Jim?
But the limit of (x^2/x) as x -> infinity is 2 (although it is still infinity divided by infinity).

The limit of (X/x^2) as x -> infinity is 0 (although again it is still infinity divided by infinity).

Both by l'Hospital's rule.

h

Joined
04 Jan 04
Moves
25350
23 Jul 06

Originally posted by Gastel
But the limit of (x^2/x) as x -> infinity is 2 (although it is still infinity divided by infinity).

The limit of (X/x^2) as x -> infinity is 0 (although again it is still infinity divided by infinity).

Both by l'Hospital's rule.
The L'Hospital's Rule that I know goes something like this:

lim f(x)/g(x) = lim f'(x)/g'(x) where f'(x) is the first derivative wrt x

So for your first example f(x) = x^2 and g(x) = x

Therefore f'(x) = 2x and g'(x) = 1

And the limit would be 2x/1 = 2x (!= 2 unless x = 1)

G

B is for bye bye

Joined
09 Apr 06
Moves
27526
23 Jul 06

Originally posted by howardbradley
The L'Hospital's Rule that I know goes something like this:

lim f(x)/g(x) = lim f'(x)/g'(x) where f'(x) is the first derivative wrt x

So for your first example f(x) = x^2 and g(x) = x

Therefore f'(x) = 2x and g'(x) = 1

And the limit would be 2x/1 = 2x (!= 2 unless x = 1)
Whoa! My bad. You are absolutely correct, I don't know where my brain is.

S

Joined
20 Feb 06
Moves
8407
23 Jul 06
6 edits

Originally posted by howardbradley
The L'Hospital's Rule that I know goes something like this:

lim f(x)/g(x) = lim f'(x)/g'(x) where f'(x) is the first derivative wrt x

So for your first example f(x) = x^2 and g(x) = x

Therefore f'(x) = 2x and g'(x) = 1

And the limit would be 2x/1 = 2x (!= 2 unless x = 1)
Well, you don't exactly need l'Hopital's rule to see

x^2/x = x

tends to infinity as x tends to infinity!

Besides all this talk of

infinity/infinity

and

something/0

is nonsense. "Infinity" is not a real number so you cannot do arbitrary operations on it. Similarly the set of real numbers form something called a field, and in a field division by zero cannot be done.

So the operations above don't exist, let alone have an answer.

If you really want to start talking about "infinity" and doing operations on "infinity" then you need to learn some set theory and start doing ordinal arithmetic or something. There you really can talk about "infinity + 1".

Search "set theory" or "ordinal arithmetic" in Wikipedia.

The approach above, like in

f(x) / g(x)

where f(x) and g(x) tend to infinity as x tends to infinity, is perfectly fine. But it has nothing to do with the spurious supposed quantity

infinity / infinity.

Instead it is merely some (separate) question in mathematical analysis to work out the answer to the limit of f(x)/g(x) as x tends to infinity.

I should finally point out that a phrase such as "x tends to infinity" does not mean "some quantity x gets closer to some other quantity infinity". Instead the *whole* phrase has a precise mathematical meaning that is quite different. (So don't analyse it using normal English).

h

Joined
04 Jan 04
Moves
25350
23 Jul 06

Originally posted by SPMars
Well, you don't exactly need l'Hopital's rule to see

x^2/x = x

tends to infinity as x tends to infinity!
I know you don't :-) Nonetheless it had been introduced, and seemingly used to prove a result that was contrary to the obvious. Since L'Hosptital is not in a position to defend himself, I thought I'd have a go.

Insanity at Masada

tinyurl.com/mw7txe34

Joined
23 Aug 04
Moves
26660
24 Jul 06

Originally posted by Gastel
But the limit of (x^2/x) as x -> infinity is 2 (although it is still infinity divided by infinity).

The limit of (X/x^2) as x -> infinity is 0 (although again it is still infinity divided by infinity).

Both by l'Hospital's rule.
But the limit of (x^2/x) as x -> infinity is 2 (although it is still infinity divided by infinity).

No, it's infinity, not 2.

a

Joined
11 Jun 06
Moves
3516
24 Jul 06

for all of you enjoying these infinity puzzles.

for any set A let T(A)= {B s.t. |B|=|A\B😏
prove that |T(R)| = 2^aleph

notation:
{ } is a set (sets are capitals)
|A| = cardinality of A
R is the set of real numbers (bold represents the basic sets, N,Z,Q,R)

B
Non-Subscriber

RHP IQ

Joined
17 Mar 05
Moves
1345
24 Jul 06
1 edit

If x were not equal to 1, then there would be infinity - 1 possible solutions for x.

Yet infinity - 1 cannot be a finite number, since no finite number plus 1 equals infinity.

S

Joined
20 Feb 06
Moves
8407
24 Jul 06
2 edits

Originally posted by aginis
for all of you enjoying these infinity puzzles.

for any set A let T(A)= {B s.t. |B|=|A\B😏
prove that |T([b]R
)| = 2^aleph

notation:
{ } is a set (sets are capitals)
|A| = cardinality of A
R is the set of real numbers (bold represents the basic sets, N,Z,Q,R)[/b]
If X is a set we let P(X) denote the power set of X, ie. the set of all subsets of X. The set R of real numbers is uncountable (and has cardinality aleph_1 = 2^(aleph_0) = |P(N)| = |R| ).
So if B is a set the only way we can have |B| = |R/B| is if B is an uncountable subset of R for which R/B is uncountable too. So we want to know the cardinality of
T(R) := { B subset of R | B and R/B are uncountable }
a subset of P(R). Well P(R) is a disjoint union of 4 subsets:
T(R) and
U := { B subset of R | B is countable and R/B is uncountable } and
V := { B subset of R | B is uncountable and R/B is countable } and
W := { B subset of R | B is countable and R/B is countable }.
Now clearly W is empty, and U, V are in bijective correspondence (via complementation) and so have the same cardinality, that of the set
X = { B subset of R | B is countable}
of countable subsets of R. Now it's easy to show |X| = |R| since

|R|

S

Joined
20 Feb 06
Moves
8407
24 Jul 06
8 edits

Sorry I typed this into notepad and it seems to have got truncated. Moreover I can't seem to complete the original details here...

Well anyhow you show the set of countable subsets of R has the same cardinality as R itself, and then it follows easily that |T(R)|=|2^R| or 2^aleph_1 if you like.

a

Joined
11 Jun 06
Moves
3516
25 Jul 06
1 edit

Originally posted by SPMars
Sorry I typed this into notepad and it seems to have got truncated. Moreover I can't seem to complete the original details here...

Well anyhow you show the set of countable subsets of R has the same cardinality as R itself, and then it follows easily that |T(R)|=|2^R| or 2^aleph_1 if you like.
I'm not sure that you are correct in saying |X| = |R|
There is a better way to answer the question, although i get your idea.
the problem is that in our discrete math class we weren't allowed to use the idea that if
|A| + |B| = 2^aleph
|A| < 2^aleph
then |B| = 2^aleph

this is because we don't know whether there exists a set with cardinality x s.t. aleph < x < 2^aleph.

HINT: the easiest way to prove that a set A has cardinality x is to show
that.
x =< |A| =< x
i.e. find a set B subset of A s.t. |B| = x and
set C s.t. |C| = x and A is a subset of C.

S

Joined
20 Feb 06
Moves
8407
25 Jul 06
7 edits

Originally posted by aginis
hmmmmm, there is a better way although i get your idea.
the problem is that in our discrete math class we weren't allowed to use the idea that if
|A| + |B| = 2^aleph
|A| < 2^aleph
then |B| = 2^aleph

this is because we don't know whether there exists a set with cardinality x s.t. aleph < x < 2^aleph.

HINT: the easiest way to prove that a set A has ...[text shortened]...
i.e. find a set B subset of A s.t. |B| = x and
set C s.t. |C| = x and A is a subset of C.
What do you mean by aleph?

aleph_1 := 2^aleph_0 := |P(N)|

I assume?

To be honest I don't see the problem with what I've done:

We have a disjoint union P(R) = T(R) U Y where Y is a subset of P(R) that has cardinality |R|. The only possibility is that |T(R)| = |P(R)|, or am I missing something?

Even if there was a set x with

| R | < |x| < |P(R)|

then we can't have |T(R)|=|x| since then |P(R)|=|T(R) U Y| < |P(R)| which is a contradiction.

a

Joined
11 Jun 06
Moves
3516
25 Jul 06

Originally posted by SPMars
What do you mean by aleph?

aleph_1 := 2^aleph_0 := |P(N)|

I assume?

To be honest I don't see the problem with what I've done:

We have P(R) = T(R) U Y where Y is a subset of P(R) that has cardinality |R|. The only possibility is that |T(R)| = |P(R)|, or am I missing something? Even if there was a set x with | R | < x
yes it could be that |T(R)| = x and x + aleph = 2^aleph
plus as i just edited the above post its not clear that |X|=aleph
(yes aleph is what you call aleph_1)

S

Joined
20 Feb 06
Moves
8407
26 Jul 06
6 edits

Originally posted by aginis
I'm not sure that you are correct in saying |X| = |R|
R is the set of real numbers.
N is the set of natural numbers.
X is the set of countable subsets of R (including the finite ones).

If C and D are sets let C^D denote the set of functions from D to C.

If C and D are sets then C < D means "there is an injection from C to D" and C=D means "there is a bijection from C to D".

We have

R < X < R^N = (2^N)^N = 2^(NxN) = 2^N = R.

The first injection is got from mapping the singleton sets into X and the second injection is got from mapping a countable subset to a function that lists its elements in increasing order (in the finite case we repeat the maximum element infinitely often).

Since we have R < X and X < R it follows from the Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem that X = R.